Metameleia in 5th and 4th century
Athenian oratory
Laurel Fulkerson
Florida State University
Despite a burgeoning interest in the passions in antiquity, certain of the
emotions remain underexplored; metameleia is one of them. The emotion of metameleia has been neglected for a variety of reasons, of which
two are key. The first derives from an only recently-discarded belief
that the Greeks, as participants in a "shame-culture" did not feel
emotions such as remorse, but were solely motivated by considerations of
utility (i.e. were concerned with punishment rather than with ethics). Although
there remains profitable discussion of the ways in which shame-cultures and
guilt-cultures might differ, and there is clearly some truth in the sentiment
put so baldly above, there is no longer a notion that it was impossible for
an Athenian to feel remorse.
A second reason for the scholarly neglect of remorse is that the places
that modern parallels might lead us to look for it, namely Athenian forensic
speeches, seem to yield poor results. Modern courtroom trials, in which
offenders regularly express remorse as a way of lightening their sentences,
differ – in this respect and others – from ancient trials, which
do not feature plea-bargaining or appeals. But, as this paper will
demonstrate, the fact that remorse plays little role in sentencing does not
mean that metameleia is unimportant
to the orators.
I will first outline the semantic field of metameleia and then discuss how it can illustrate both Athenian
morality and the techniques used by fifth- and fourth-century orators to
lead their audiences to draw certain conclusions. I will argue that metameleia serves in forensic oratory to distance the object
of the speaker's attack from the speaker and from the judges (conceived
of as a unitary moral force) and also, in other forms of oratory, to act
as a check on the Athenian people themselves. In both cases, it is
used as a tool to manipulate the audience into finding certain propositions
repugnant and their opposites desirable. It will be seen that remorse
fills a much larger function; it is central to morality and serves as a
signifier of moral conscience.